Dedekind Cuts, Constructing R

The idea of dedekind cuts is the following. Consider the real line:

The idea here is to think of A as all valid rational approximations of 2. We wish we could say the suprema of A is 2 but we can't. But what if we say that R includes all of these suprema?

Cut

A subset AQ is a cut if it satisfies the following:

  1. A and AQ (strict, non-trivial subsets)
  2. If aA and qQ is such that q<a, then qA (all lower terms at the 'sup' are in the set)
  3. If aA then qA such that q>a (there is no rational maximum 'approximation')
Cr={tQ|t<r} is always a cut

The set Cr described is always a cut for rQ.

Proof
Let rQ be arbitrary. We'll prove all the conditions:

  1. Clearly r1<r so rCr and thus we have an element (so Cr). Further we know that r+1Cr so CrQ.
  2. Let aCr and qQ where q<a. Since aCr then a<r. Thus then q<r, so clearly qCr
  3. If aCr then choose q=a+r2. Clearly qQ while q>a and still q<r so then qA as needed.
Examples/Nonexamples of Dedekind Cuts

a. S={tQ|t2} is not a Dedekind cut because 2 is a rational maximum.
b. T={tQ|t2<2t<0} is a Dedekind cut (as we'll use variations of)
c. U={tQ|t22t<0} is still a Dedekind cut
For in-depth explanations of these see [[AbbotSolns.pdf#page=246]].

R as a construction

Define R={AQ:A is a cut}

Recall the R theorem:

R

R

an ordered field R which contains Q which satisfies the the axiom of completeness.

Where the axiom of completeness:

axiom of completeness

The Axiom of Completeness

Every nonempty set of real numbers that is bounded above has a least upper bound.

The idea here is that every irrational number will be identified by a cut set A, where since the cut has a least upper bound, then R contains it as well.

References \

  1. [[Abbott Real Analysis.pdf#page=298]]