Proof
Assume for contradiction that is rational, so then:
for some where and don't share any common factors. Squaring both sides gives that:
so , or has a factor of . Notice that because of that:
so then since then clearly so then set for some so then:
so then is divisible by , and by the same argument which contradicts not sharing any factors.
☐
Note that the argument would follow similarly for , except that when we breakup notice that 6 isn't prime so then we'll get:
so we show that is either divisible by 2 or by 3 and continue the argument to show that shares the same factor.
but this couldn't lead to a contradiction as so then so then:
which doesn't give a contradiction.
1.2.3
a
Postulate
If are all sets with an infinite number of elements, then is infinite as well.
This is a false statement. Consider the superset , and have defined by:
We can see that so then by that definition then as required. But all of these sets are uncountably infinite, but notice that . This is because if there were some then I can construct a new set where:
where clearly is in our sequence of sets, but by definition. But this larger set is finite in length (length 0) which is a counter example to the postulate at hand.
b
Postulate
If are all sets with finite number of elements, then is finite as well.
This is a true statement. Namely, we know that if then which is finite, and in general then so then clearly is finite.
c
Postulate
This is a false statement. Let and . Notice that:
but:
and these don't equal.
d
Postulate
This is a true statement. For let so then and so and . Then and thus . The other direction is proved similarly WLOG.
e
Postulate
This is a true statement.
. Let . Then and . If then so then . Then if then by requirement so then similarly and is in the RHS set. Thus we get .
. Let be in the RHS set. Suppose so then and . Then so then . WLOG the same applies for .
1.2.5 (De Morgan's Laws)
a
Theorem
Proof
Let . Then . For one case if then we must have that so then so then . If instead then and we get the same result.
☐
b
Theorem
Proof
Let . If then , so clearly . Thus, then . WLOG, the same applies if .
☐
c
Theorem
Proof
First . Let . Then . Notice if then that's a contradiction and same for , so then and so then .
Then . Let , thus and . Then and . Notice by similar reasoning prior that so .
☐
1.2.7
Given function and a subset of its domain , we denote as the range of over set .
a
Given and and then we know that:
so then:
while:
so in this case . Similarly
while:
so in this case.
b
In general we don't have . For instance, if and then:
here clearly .
c
Theorem
For any then .
Proof
Let be arbitrary. Then there is some such that by definition. Clearly and . Thus, since then since and likewise . Thus, , completing the proof.
☐
1.2.9
Given some and a subset , denote as the preimage, namely:
a
Let . If is the closed interval and is the closed interval then:
Notice that:
while:
so in this case . Similarly:
while:
so then in this case.
b
Theorem
For any then:
for all sets .
Proof
We prove the former.
. Let . Then there is some by definition. Then and separately. Thus then and similar for , so then .
. Let . Then and similar for . Then there is some and likewise . Thus . Thus, .
For the latter:
. Let . Then there's some . If then so then . WLOG, the same can be sead if instead (ie: ).
. Let . If then so then so then . WLOG, the same works if instead.
☐
1.2.11
We'll negate certain statements into their opposites:
a
The opposite of "for all reals where then there is some where " is:
"there are reals where, for any , we have it that ".
Here the original claim is true, as we can always choose some lowest fraction that's less than some .
b
The opposite of "there is a real such that for all " is:
Proof
We prove this via induction. The base case for is just the simpler De Morgan's Law from 1.2 - Set Theory Review#1.2.5 (De Morgan's Laws)#c. Let be arbitrary, and suppose the theorem holds for . Consider the case, then:
Since the LHS set is composed of sets and the RHS set is just one set, we can use our Inductive Hypothesis:
completing the proof by induction.
☐
b
We'll show that induction can't always be used. We'll show that for some but . Let . Here any finite intersection allows us to find some in that intersection, but intersecting all infinitely many sets, as we saw in 1.2 - Set Theory Review#1.2.3#a that we get the empty set.
c
Theorem
Proof
We prove first. Let be an element of the LHS. Then . That means that there isn't any set where . Hence, for all sets then , so then for all these sets. Hence, then as required.
Now for . Let be an element of the RHS. Then for all . Hence, then for all . Then there doesn't exist any sets where so then . Hence, is in the LHS.
☐